In
regards to economic policy, Blinder makes a persuasive argument that
market-based approaches to pollution-reduction are more effective in reducing
costs and emissions politicians or the rigid mandates of environmental
agencies. Blinder explains, “The
main reason why direct controls cost society so much more than pollution fees,
you will recall, is that there are disparities from firm to firm in pollution
abatement” (152). Specifically, certain firms will find it much more costly to
reduce emissions than other firms, and free-market approaches, unlike
straight-jacket mandates, can use this discrepancy to help lessen the economic
burdens on firms while still producing the same outcome. For example, if firm
Pear-Picking can lower emissions at a meager marginal cost of $5, whereas the
Shoe-Scrubbing firm must spend $500 dollars to make an equal reduction, an
emissions market would efficiently allocate the pollution reduction to the Pear-Pickers.
Thus, by taking advantage of different firms’ varying marginal cost of
emissions reduction, a minimal burden on the market can be achieved.
While I agree thus far with
Blinder’s logic, I would like to point out an important complexity that Blinder
calls the “bubble concept.” Blinder explains that the more firms (and
potentially types of pollutants) that are incorporated into the emissions
trading circle, the more efficient the market will become. If more firms are
able to trade their emissions permits, the firm with the lowest marginal cost
for emissions reduction will be compensated by the other firms to do so,
resulting in a healthier environment at a limited cost to the economy.
Similarly, if x amount of carbon
emissions are found to have the same detrimental effect on the environment as y amount of methane gas, firms may
individually, and through trading, collectively, weigh the potential burden to
reducing each pollutant and make the most efficient plan in acquiring the
desired decrease in pollutant production. However, how wide exactly should we
open this market? To minimize reduction-costs, the answer would be, completely
open. If one firm can reduce admissions at a lower cost, then by all means they
should do it. However, another
consideration exists in tension with the principal of maximizing effiency. If I
live in California, I may not particularly care that an environmental policy
will reduce CO2 emissions in New York, or in South Africa. Consider the
following example illustrated by the relative costs of carbon emissions price
in Sweden and Germany. While this graph illustrates the relative carbon taxes,
not the actual marginal cost of reduction, for my purposes this is not
important. As illustrated by the relative slopes, Germany can reduce its
emissions at a much lower cost than Sweden. In this Figure, Req = required
emissions reductions. In this example, Germany has an opportunity to profit if
it reduces more emissions than required and sells these permits to Sweden, who
are incentivized to buy them because internal costs of reduction are higher. Thus,
Sweden makes cuts costs by buying emission permits from Germany and Germany
profits. Everyone wins! J
The potential problem here though is that Sweden citizens
would be living in an environment where more pollution exists. It may be true
that some forms of emissions
affect citizens of the world equally (Green House Gases may), but other
pollutants affect local regions more severely. Smog in LA is a testament to
this truth. LA citizens may rightfully be unhappy, then, if the trading
“bubble” of emissions permits are expanded to include state, country, or even
international markets. The fact that pollutant externalities effect local
pollutions more severely pulls against the economic motive to have entirely
free markets and should be closely considered and weighed against cost
considerations when making policy decisions.
No comments:
Post a Comment